Thought: a different perspective
Marc D. Hauser1
1. Department
of Psychology, Harvard University, 33 Kirkland Street, Cambridge, Massachusetts
02138, USA
Sir
Patricia Churchland's review of Steven Pinker's latest book The
Stuff of Thought ('Poetry in motion' Nature 450, 29–30; 2007) offers
scant information about the book, and what there is is incorrect. Churchland
instead presents her own views on how molecular biology and neurobiology
provide challenges to Pinker, but in so doing she undermines the successes of
these disciplines. She concludes that Pinker's book is only about semantics and
that his discussion of the mind represents a kind of madman nativist perspective,
ignoring the role of the environment and research in the neurosciences.
I have the impression that Churchland restricted her reading to
the prologue, heaving the book across the room in dismay while ejaculating
"Same old, same old!" Otherwise, she would surely have come across
Pinker's detailed analysis of the evolution and development of the core
conceptual structures of space, time, number and cause, and how these
building-blocks enable the child to acquire not only a lexicon, but also an understanding
of the world. This view doesn't eliminate either experience or cultural
processes, but rather shows ways in which a core architecture may constrain the
acquisition of knowledge and lead to a suite of shared mental capacities.
She would also have come across rich and entertaining chapters on
naming our children, swearing (I refrain), and the pragmatics of bargains,
bribes and other social conventions. And throughout, Pinker mentions work in
the neurosciences. This includes studies of people with brain damage, cellular
recordings of animals and humans, and imaging experiments; some of these Pinker
conducted himself with colleagues and students.
But these ideas are sometimes controversial, and it saddened me
that the Book Review did not discuss why. Instead, it went into challenges
apparently posed by genetics and neurobiology for the cognitive sciences, and
particularly for the brain-as-merely-hardware kind that Pinker is said to
peddle.
Take, for example, Churchland's assertion that "extravagant claims
about human uniqueness must deal with the discovery that humans have only about
28,000 genes, and differ from mice in just 300 or so". (Not so: humans
have only about 300 genes not found in mice, but the others aren't identical.)
Even if accurate, this would not constitute an argument against any of Pinker's
book. In fact, it shows why one has to be careful in interpreting the
relationship between genomic sequence overlap and phenotypic similarity. The
monumental cognitive gap between mice and humans tells us that the number of
homologous genes and the percentage of sequence overlap are simplistic measures
of species similarity, rather than the genomic overlap telling us that humans
are cognitively equivalent to mice.
We have to look to another story to explain how, given such overlap, we are so different. The point is magnified when we consider the 98% overlap with chimpanzees, and again, the spectacular differences in our cognitive abilities, ranging from the expression of language, music and mathematics, to the creation of soufflˇs, Global Positioning System navigators and humour. I hope the readers of Nature will dig into Pinker's book, even if it is only to learn what he said.